登陆注册
10812000000005

第5章

Zeno and the Tortoise The use of reductio ad absurdurn

There is a common suspicion in the more refined bar rooms that homophobia, far from denoting red-blooded heterosexuality, in fact belies an inability to cope with one's own repressed homosexual leanings. But if hatred of others springs from hatred of oneself, then by the same token we would expect Ku Klux Klan members, for example, to have a repressed African-American side to their personality. This line of ridicule is known as reductio ad absurdum, which means literally 'reduce to absurdity'. We use this device whenever, instead of arguing that a position is untrue, we examine what would follow if it were correct in order to derive unacceptable results. In ordinary life, ridiculing someone else's argument is certainly easier than constructing a position of one's own. It is no different in philosophy. Where we must wait for the passage of time to reveal the absurdity of a government policy or an over-hasty marriage, in logical argument the process is altogether quicker.

The first philosopher to employ reductio ad absurdum was Zeno, who (according to Plato) was a tall and graceful Greek born around 490 BC in Elea, a town now in southern Italy. Zeno was a pupil of the philosopher Parmenides, who taught that all the many and varied things that seem to exist are actually a single everlasting reality that he called 'being'. He argued that the negation of being, along with any imagined changes it might undergo, is in fact impossible. Only about two hundred words of Zeno's writings survive, but it seems that as a young man he wrote a work of philosophy with which he may not have been entirely pleased and which was circulated without his knowledge. The book did, however, make him famous in faraway Athens. Plato relates that Parmenides and Zeno visited the city together in around 450 BC where they met the young Socrates. Zeno stayed a while, charging noblemen for the privilege of listening to him hold forth. According to legend, he became involved in politics on his return to Elea and plotted to overthrow the city's tyrant, Nearchus. Before the conspirators could act, Zeno was arrested and tortured to death for his treason. Several stories tell of his interrogation. In one, he named the tyrant's friends as his co-conspirators rather than betraying his accomplices. In others, he bit off his tongue and spat it at Nearchus or even leaped upon the tyrant and bit off his nose. These tales are not as far-fetched as Zeno's own philosophy.

Zeno wanted to prove that the multiplicity that the world exhibits was an illusion and that reality was composed of an eternally unchanging oneness. He disavowed any notion of time, motion or any kind of plurality among objects. He attacked our ordinary notions of space and time by assuming their truth and taking the consequences as far as they would go. The result of Zeno's efforts was a collection of forty paradoxes. Most of these have been lost, but three of them in particular have been causing problems for philosophers and mathematicians for two and a half millennia.

The most famous of Zeno's paradoxes is the story of a race between Achilles and the tortoise. Since Achilles is a very fast runner, the tortoise is given a ten-yard head-start. This may not sound terribly generous to the tortoise, but in fact it is enough to win him the contest. When the race begins, Achilles is quick off the mark and soon makes up those ten yards. By this time the tortoise has managed to advance just one yard, which Achilles then covers in a single bound. Now, however, the tortoise has managed to advance a further three inches. Picking up speed, Achilles crosses those inches only to find that the tortoise has moved on an extra inch. By the time Achilles traverses that inch, the tortoise will in turn have advanced some further distance, albeit a very short one. Zeno argues that no matter how fast Achilles runs he will never be able to overtake his rival, because in order to do so he must first draw level with him. This can never be achieved because as long as it takes Achilles some time – however little – to reach the tortoise's position, the creature will have had time to move on a fraction. Though the distance separating them draws ever shorter, it can never dwindle to nothing. The tortoise will therefore remain in the lead for ever.

If this is not frustrating enough for Achilles, things get even worse for him in the paradox of the racetrack. In order to reach the end of a course, Achilles would first have to reach the halfway mark. After that, the remaining distance would have its own halfway mark to be reached. The final quarter can also be divided into two, and so on, it seems, for ever. To get to the finishing line, Achilles would have to travel through an infinite number of divisions of the track. Since each one of these segments must comprise some distance and take some time, however minute, to cross, it will take him for ever to finish the course. Each segment may be very small, but an infinite number of them will make for an infinite distance. Fortunately, or unfortunately, Achilles will not have to worry about running until the end of time as, by the same reasoning, he will never be able to begin running. The first half of the track can also be divided ad infinitum, so before Achilles can cover half the distance he must first cover a quarter of it, and before that an eighth and so on … Since there is no end to these fractions, it will take him literally for ever to leave the starting blocks.

According to the paradox of the arrow, these problems can be put aside because nothing ever moves. The flight of an arrow can be divided into instants, which are the smallest possible measure of time. If the arrow moves during one of these instants, it means that it begins the instant in one place and ends in another. In this case we would not be talking about an instant at all because the moment could be divided further. Once we have alighted on a true instant – a moment that by definition cannot be divided further – then we have a division of time in which no movement can take place. This, however, means that the arrow can never move, as no amount of no-motion can add up to motion. Since the arrow does not move in any single point in its flight, it does not move over the whole flight.

The arrow is the easiest of the paradoxes to tackle. Motion requires time, so it is not surprising that if you take away time and talk instead of instants then you also take away motion. Though the arrow may not move in any given instant, it can still move if motion is defined as a thing's appearance in a different place at a later point in time. The paradoxes involving Achilles and the tortoise are more difficult. They can still be avoided, Zeno argued, by dismissing the very notion of divisibility. If this offends common sense, he thought, then too bad for common sense. It is clearly unsatisfactory, however, to replace one absurdity with another as Zeno does. Fortunately, we can escape from the predicament by using mathematical tools that were not available to the philosopher and his contemporaries in the fifth century BC. We now know it to be a mistake to suppose that a distance composed of an infinite number of finite parts must itself be infinite. If we were to construct a series which added ? to ? to ? and so on for ever, most mathematicians would avow that the total is one, not infinity. There is therefore nothing impossible in space being infinitely divisible. Neither is there a problem with crossing an infinite number of segments of a racecourse in a finite time. By this thinking, then, Achilles can leave his starting blocks and overtake the tortoise unhindered before being shot in the heel with a well-aimed arrow.

Zeno was a 'strong' user of reductio because he took a set of beliefs and derived logical impossibilities from them. But one does not have to come up with paradoxes to stay true to the method. 'Weaker' reductios may involve consequences that are merely unacceptable rather than impossible. A pro-life philosopher, for example, might reject any moral system the tenets of which imply support for abortion even if such support is not explicitly articulated. Or a political theorist might dismiss revolutionary communism because it can countenance the death of innocents as a justifiable means to an end even though its adherents do not hold the right to murder as a core principle. On this level, reductio ad absurdum is little more than an arguing technique, as one man's absurdity might not seem so ridiculous to another. The point goes beyond matters of moral taste – such as abortion – into the purely logical. The German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) argued that theft was wrong because such behaviour could not be universalized. That is, if everyone went around stealing things it would undermine the convention of property that makes theft possible in the first place. This reductio would not convince everyone, but it would convince a thief least of all. A similar argument was presented to Yossarian, the hero of Joseph Heller's Catch-22, when he refused to fly in any more bombing raids. 'What would happen,' his commanding officer asked, 'if everyone refused to fly?' 'Then I'd be a damn fool to do any different,' Yossarian replied. The efficacy of reductio ad absurdum depends in a large part upon shared notions of the ridiculous.

An equally important issue for all kinds of reductio is whether absurdities that arise in extreme situations should be allowed to impinge upon beliefs that hold true in ordinary circumstances. For example, many people believe that there is no harm in the occasional use of marijuana and that the law against the drug infringes their liberty. The anti-drugs lobby routinely counters that if the law allowed people to do anything they wanted, society would break down. This may well be true, but it is a consequence far removed from smoking the occasional joint. The charge that someone is taking a point to extremes is normally sufficient to blunt the force of a reductio in ordinary life. For the most part, the further a reductio is taken towards the extreme, the less we feel bound to take notice of its upshot. This may be due to cynicism rather than credulity, since there might be no position that cannot be reduced to some form of absurdity or another.

The other defence against reductio is to claim that one's beliefs are not philosophical ones. That is, they are about specific concerns rather than lofty generalities. So an explanation of homophobia does not have to explain every other kind of hatred. What is true of homophobes may not be true of race-baiting rednecks, though it is possible the two might sometimes be one and the same. However, to defend an explanation is also to defend the method used to construct it. In our original case, this is the dubious principle that all hatred is really self-hatred. Ultimately, for reductio to work it is necessary for both sides to agree on what conclusions count as 'unacceptable'. For that reason, the approach may be unlikely ever to convince the proponents of soft-drug legalization.

同类推荐
  • The Ecology of Law

    The Ecology of Law

    In the past few decades, science has shifted from seeing the natural world as a kind of cosmic machine best understood by analyzing each cog and sprocket to a systems perspective that views the world as a vast network of fluid communities and studies their dynamic interactions.
  • Worst Laid Plans
  • Poor Folk(III)穷人(英文版)

    Poor Folk(III)穷人(英文版)

    Poor Folk is the first novel by Fyodor Dostoyevsky, written over the span of nine months between 1844 and 1845. Inspired by the works of Gogol, Pushkin, and Karamzin, as well as English and French authors, Poor Folk is written in the form of letters between the two main characters, Makar Devushkin and Varvara Dobroselova, who are poor second cousins. The novel showcases the life of poor people, their relationship with rich people, and poverty in general, all common themes of literary naturalism. A deep but odd friendship develops between them until Dobroselova loses her interest in literature, and later in communicating with Devushkin after a rich widower Mr. Bykov proposes to her. While Vissarion Belinsky dubbed the novel Russia's first "social novel" and Alexander Herzen called it a major socialist work, other critics detected parody and satire.
  • Undertown
  • Soups (Sheila Lukins Short eCookbooks)

    Soups (Sheila Lukins Short eCookbooks)

    For over twenty years, PARADE food editor, writer, and chef Sheila Lukins has inspired would-be chefs across the country with her accessible and easy-to-prepare Simply Delicious recipes. This e-cookbook is a compilation of Sheila's favorite chicken recipes from her time at PARADE, written with the busy home cook in mind.In addition to dozens of creative and succulent chicken recipes, this book provides an easy tutorial on how to roast the perfect chicken and carve poultry at the table. Readers get plenty of delicious and fun ideas for jazzing up a weeknight chicken dinner or creating the perfect special-occasion meal—that are sure to delight the entire family.
热门推荐
  • 追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    青涩蜕变,如今她是能独当一面的女boss,爱了冷泽聿七年,也同样花了七年时间去忘记他。以为是陌路,他突然向他表白,扬言要娶她,她只当他是脑子抽风,他的殷勤她也全都无视。他帮她查她父母的死因,赶走身边情敌,解释当初拒绝她的告别,和故意对她冷漠都是无奈之举。突然爆出她父母的死居然和冷家有丝毫联系,还莫名跳出个公爵未婚夫,扬言要与她履行婚约。峰回路转,破镜还能重圆吗? PS:我又开新文了,每逢假期必书荒,新文《有你的世界遇到爱》,喜欢我的文的朋友可以来看看,这是重生类现言,对这个题材感兴趣的一定要收藏起来。
  • 你似春风百花闻

    你似春风百花闻

    顾桃上辈子死于车祸临死前一秒发现她早就爱上了苏沐辰从来一世回到高中她决定好好生活好好爱他eve甜宠全书无虐处高冷学霸少女vs傲娇怪味男孩苏沐辰:你似春风百花闻一掠山河万木生顾桃:上辈子我错过你了,这辈子我一定紧紧抓住你的手绝不放开
  • 季羡林谈翻译(典藏本)

    季羡林谈翻译(典藏本)

    季羡林先生不仅是我国的著名学者,而且是大翻译家。他精通多种外语,译著丰富,在长期的翻译工作中,积累了丰富的经验,提出了很多独到而精辟的翻译理论和观点。《季羡林谈翻译(典藏本)》精选了季羡林先生谈翻译的文章,生动有趣,活泼精炼,蕴含着深刻的道理,对学习外文和从事翻译工作的读者有所帮助。
  • 青梅小甜妻,竹马远一点

    青梅小甜妻,竹马远一点

    从小学就开始翘课,上课吃东西,拿粉笔砸老师……在别人眼里,她是一个样样都会的无良少女而他是一个温柔的佳公子,家世好样貌好学历好性格好什么都好的十全十美的男人。至少表面上是这样。但是实际如何.....怕也只有她才知道了。
  • 秘令:黑衣特警侦破密案纪实

    秘令:黑衣特警侦破密案纪实

    本书主要以发生在北京的大案要案为故事素材:徐虎与“梨园弟子”宣北平、于燕华的贩毒案;“陆军上尉”的贩枪案;“老鬼”绑架人质撕票案;云上人间、紫丁香夜总会涉嫌洗钱卖淫案;李局等人贪污腐化堕落案,等等。全书将这些真实的案件、真实的人物放到真实的社会大环境中,在环环紧扣的故事悬念之中,展现了公安特警季枫、章大为、周可心、李同、李寻、曹轶等人与罪犯斗智斗勇的精彩画面,说明了正义战胜邪恶是颠扑不破的真理。
  • 追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    青涩蜕变,如今她是能独当一面的女boss,爱了冷泽聿七年,也同样花了七年时间去忘记他。以为是陌路,他突然向他表白,扬言要娶她,她只当他是脑子抽风,他的殷勤她也全都无视。他帮她查她父母的死因,赶走身边情敌,解释当初拒绝她的告别,和故意对她冷漠都是无奈之举。突然爆出她父母的死居然和冷家有丝毫联系,还莫名跳出个公爵未婚夫,扬言要与她履行婚约。峰回路转,破镜还能重圆吗? PS:我又开新文了,每逢假期必书荒,新文《有你的世界遇到爱》,喜欢我的文的朋友可以来看看,这是重生类现言,对这个题材感兴趣的一定要收藏起来。
  • 盛世娇宠:妖女为后

    盛世娇宠:妖女为后

    君卿卿,上一世被枕边人和胞妹陷害醉死酒中,亡国灭族,死得不甘不愿。再次睁开眼,已是将军嫡女携一身秘术归来,一只横笛御虫蛊,素手执棋,谋划天下。只为逝去的亲人和万千子民讨一个公道。萧宁煜,一代冷血战神踏雪而来,上不谋天,下不谋地,只为谋与她并肩看江山无限,此生共度。一觉起来,某女不屑的暼了一眼得了便宜还卖乖的某王,她又不是肥羊这个男人为什么吃干抹净以后还要一副饿狼的眼光盯着她?“没想到本王跟你睡一夜,竟然得了十万雄兵。”某王摸摸下巴意犹未尽:“本王想着…这倒是个不错的长期买卖。”
  • 蒋氏家族全传

    蒋氏家族全传

    蒋介石在中国近代历史上是一位毁誉兼有的人物。本书详细记述了蒋介石的生平、婚姻家庭和军政生涯,涉及身世秘密、辛亥革命、上海证券交易所工作、黄埔军校时期、北伐战争、四一二反革命政变、蒋宋联姻、统一中国、围剿红军、西安事变、抗日战争、国共决战、退守台湾、传位蒋经国等内容。本书客观地描述了蒋介石领导北伐统一中国以及领导抗战抵御外侮的历史功绩,同时指出,蒋介石的独裁统治、政府的腐化堕落、民心的丧失是其失去政权的重要原因。
  • 追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    追妻无门:女boss不好惹

    青涩蜕变,如今她是能独当一面的女boss,爱了冷泽聿七年,也同样花了七年时间去忘记他。以为是陌路,他突然向他表白,扬言要娶她,她只当他是脑子抽风,他的殷勤她也全都无视。他帮她查她父母的死因,赶走身边情敌,解释当初拒绝她的告别,和故意对她冷漠都是无奈之举。突然爆出她父母的死居然和冷家有丝毫联系,还莫名跳出个公爵未婚夫,扬言要与她履行婚约。峰回路转,破镜还能重圆吗? PS:我又开新文了,每逢假期必书荒,新文《有你的世界遇到爱》,喜欢我的文的朋友可以来看看,这是重生类现言,对这个题材感兴趣的一定要收藏起来。
  • 网王之美人带刺

    网王之美人带刺

    世人皆知,被花逸抛弃的少年少女数不胜数,所以都说她是渣女,花逸听了,微微一笑“小女子,没见过什么大世面,一生只爱一张脸”