登陆注册
5391600000050

第50章 ANALYTIC OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT(17)

But the sublime in nature-if we pass upon it a pure aesthetic judgement unmixed with concepts of perfection, as objective finality, which would make the judgement teleological-may be regarded as completely wanting in form or figure, and none the less be looked upon as an object of pure delight, and indicate a subjective finality of the given representation.So, now, the question suggests itself, whether in addition to the exposition of what is thought in an aesthetic judgement of this kind, we may be called upon to give a deduction of its claim to some (subjective) a priori principle.

This we may meet with the reply that the sublime in nature is improperly so called, and that sublimity should, in strictness, be attributed merely to the attitude of thought, or, rather, to that which serves as basis for this in human nature.The apprehension of an object otherwise formless and in conflict with ends supplies the mere occasion for our coming to a consciousness of this basis; and the object is in this way put to a subjectively-final use, but it is not estimated as subjectively-final on its own account and because of its form.(It is, as it were, a species finalis accepta, non data.)Consequently the exposition we gave of judgements upon the sublime in nature was at the same time their deduction.For, in our analysis of the reflection on the part of judgement in this case, we found that in such judgements there is a final relation of the cognitive faculties, which has to be laid a priori at the basis of the faculty of ends (the will), and which is therefore itself a priori final.

This, then, at once involves the deduction, i.e., the justification of the claim of such a judgement to universally-necessary validity.

Hence we may confine our search to one for the deduction of judgements of taste, i.e., of judgements upon the beauty of things of nature, and this will satisfactorily dispose of the problem for the entire aesthetic faculty of judgement.

SS 31.Of the method of the deduction of judgements of taste.

The obligation to furnish a deduction, i.e., a guarantee of the legitimacy of judgements of a particular kind, only arises where the judgement lays claim to necessity.This is the case even where it requires subjective universality, i.e., the concurrence of every one, albeit the judgement is not a cognitive judgement, but only one of pleasure or displeasure in a given object, i.e., an assumption of a subjective finality that has a thoroughgoing validity for every one, and which, since the judgement is one of taste, is not to be grounded upon any concept of the thing.

Now, in the latter case, we are not dealing with a judgement of cognition-neither with a theoretical one based on the concept of a nature in general, supplied by understanding, nor with a (pure)practical one based on the idea of freedom, as given a priori by reason-and so we are not called upon to justify a priori the validity of a judgement which represents either what a thing is, or that there is something which I ought to do in order to produce it.

Consequently, if for judgement generally we demonstrate the universal validity of a singular judgement expressing the subjective finality of an empirical representation of the form of an object, we shall do all that is needed to explain how it is possible that something can please in the mere formation of an estimate of it (without sensation or concept), and how, just as the estimate of an object for the sake of a cognition generally has universal rules, the delight of any one person may be pronounced as a rule for every other.

Now if this universal validity is not to be based on a collection of votes and interrogation of others as to what sort of sensations they experience, but is to rest, as it were, upon an, autonomy of the subject passing judgement on the feeling of pleasure (in the given representation), i.e., upon his own taste, and yet is also not to be derived from concepts; then it follows that such a judgement-and such the judgement of taste in fact is-has a double and also logical peculiarity.For, first, it has universal validity a priori, yet without having a logical universality according to concepts, but only the universality of a singular judgement.Secondly, it has a necessity (which must invariably rest upon a priori grounds), but one which depends upon no a priori proofs by the representation of which it would be competent to enforce the assent which the judgement of taste demands of every one.

The solution of these logical peculiarities, which distinguish a judgement of taste from all cognitive judgements, will of itself suffice for a deduction of this strange faculty, provided we abstract at the outset from all content of the judgement, viz., from the feeling of pleasure, and merely compare the aesthetic form with the form of objective judgements as prescribed by logic.We shall first try, with the help of examples, to illustrate and bring out these characteristic properties of taste.

SS 32.First peculiarity of the judgement of taste.

The judgement of taste determines its object in respect of delight (as a thing of beauty) with a claim to the agreement of every one, just as if it were objective.

To say: "this flower is beautiful is tantamount to repeating its own proper claim to the delight of everyone.The agreeableness of its smell gives it no claim at all.One man revels in it, but it gives another a headache.Now what else are we to suppose from this than that its beauty is to be taken for a property of the flower itself which does not adapt itself to the diversity of heads and the individual senses of the multitude, but to which they must adapt themselves, if they are going to pass judgement upon it.And yet this is not the way the matter stands.For the judgement of taste consists precisely in a thing being called beautiful solely in respect of that quality in which it adapts itself to our mode of taking it in.

同类推荐
热门推荐
  • 念你的每一天都是晨曦

    念你的每一天都是晨曦

    她定睛细看,发现窗外不知什么时候飘满了五颜六色的心型气球,糖果般美丽透明的颜色,缤纷得如同夏日最轻盈甜美的梦境。这是熙南爱的告白吗?
  • 明天下

    明天下

    明末的历史纷乱混杂,堪称是一段由一些有着强大个人魅力的人书写成的历史。不论是李自成,还是张献忠这些叛逆者,还是崇祯,袁崇焕,这些当权者,亦或是吴三桂,耿精忠这些背叛者,每个人身上都有很多的故事,就是因为有了这些精彩的故事,明末的历史才变得大气起磅礴,波澜起伏。想要把这一段历史写好,自然要描绘出一个个活生生的人物,不论他的立场如何,我们站在历史长河的边缘上旁观,他们不过是这条长河里的一朵浪花。冷眼看世界,就是我们目前需要做的事情,冷眼看历史也是我们目前生活的一种追求。历史长河已经流淌到了我们的脚下,我们大可站在河边,准备迎接我们的历史。
  • 杨那张帆

    杨那张帆

    在普通的学校中有一个小人物,在校园中成名后进入社会中摸爬滚打,会有什么样的故事呢……
  • Winesburg Ohio

    Winesburg Ohio

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。汇聚授权电子版权。
  • 芋香

    芋香

    我和隋唐是同村人,都住在一个四面环山,中间低洼的地方。我住中庄,隋唐住下庄。在同一条河里吃水,在同一座山上捡柴,在同一处庙中烧香。我俩的村庄叫散岔。
  • 我的右手能吸收

    我的右手能吸收

    天地异变,觉醒右手。楚风的右手有了神奇的吸收能力…吸收熊的特长,力量爆涨。吸收鹰的天赋,视力狂增。吸收了豹的能力,速度飙长…蚂蚁可以举起超过自己体重400倍的物体,跳蚤可以跳过它们身长350倍的距离,壁虎的断肢可以短时间重新生长,变色龙的皮肤可以变幻颜色……这些,都将成为他的天赋!
  • 星球大战:塔金

    星球大战:塔金

    在帝国时代早期,星区总督威尔赫夫·塔金受命和维达去调查一起叛乱事件。这是一个陷阱,塔金先进的战舰“腐肉尖峰号”被身份不明的反抗派劫持,并到处实施破坏。塔金总督和达斯·维达一路跟踪,追击叛乱的战舰。随着一步步真相大白,故事抽丝剥茧地回答了这个问题:塔金这位制造过多次血腥镇压的铁腕总督,为什么一直坚持恐惧统治的理想?他的成长史,他的所思所想,他的立场与原则,虽然出于虚幻的想象,却有着坚实的现实土壤,让人警醒,使人沉思。
  • 怀紫阁隐者

    怀紫阁隐者

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。汇聚授权电子版权。
  • 超神学院的天道

    超神学院的天道

    某绝世男子:我要逆天~~!叶无忧:MMP,老子惹你了吗?你就要逆我?说着随手一个神雷摔下,砸死了某绝世男子。
  • 人性的优点

    人性的优点

    戴尔·卡耐基是20世纪伟大的成功学大师和心灵导师,《人性的优点》汇集了卡耐基的思想精华,是作者最成功的励志经典。本书从人性的角度,挖掘出潜藏在人们体内的弱点,使人们能够充分认识自己,并不断改造自己,从而能有所长进,直至取得最后的成功。不论你是什么职业,也不论性别、年龄。这本充满力量和智慧的书,在生活中一定会给你以启迪,使你勇敢地克服自己的弱点,拥有美好、快乐、成功的人生。